|
Restorative justice: the real story - Kathleen Daly - School of Criminology and Criminal Justice - Griffith University - Brisbane, Qld12 July 2001 +61 7 3875-5625 3216-1630 (ho) k.daly@mailbox.gu.edu.au Forthcoming in Punishment & Society Acknowledgments This paper is revised from a plenary address given to the Scottish Criminology Conference, Edinburgh, 21-22 September 2000. My thanks to the conference organisers, Lesley McAra and David J. Smith, for the invitation; and to Emilios Christodoulidis, Neil Hutton, Ian Loader, Richard Sparks, and the anonymous reviewers for their comments on earlier versions. KATHLEEN DALY is Associate Professor, School of Criminology and Criminal Justice, Griffith University, Brisbane. She directed a major research project on conferencing in South Australia in 1998-99, and has begun a second major project on the feminist and indigenous/race politics of restorative justice in Australia, New Zealand, Canada, and the United States. Among her publications are Gender, Crime, and Punishment (Yale University Press, 1994) and an edited collection, with Lisa Maher, Criminology at the Crossroads: Feminist Readings in Crime and Justice (Oxford University Press, 1998). 1 Restorative justice: the real story Abstract Advocates' claims about restorative justice contain four myths: (1) restorative justice is the opposite of retributive justice, (2) restorative justice uses indigenous justice practices and was the dominant form of pre-modern justice, (3) restorative justice is a 'care' (or feminine) response to crime in comparison to a 'justice' (or masculine) response, and (4) restorative justice can be expected to produce major changes in people. Drawing from research on conferencing in Australia and New Zealand, I show that the real story of restorative justice differs greatly from advocates' mythical true story. Despite what advocates say, there areconnections between retribution and restoration (or reparation), restorative justice should not be considered a pre-modern and feminine justice, strong stories of repair and goodwill are uncommon, and the raw material for restorativeness between victims and offenders may be in short supply. Following Engel (1993: 791-92), myth refers to a true story; its truth deals with 'origins, with birth, with beginnings ... with how something began to be'. Origin stories, in turn, 'encode a set of oppositions' (p. 821) such that when telling a true story, speakers transcend adversity'. By comparing advocates' true story of restorative justice with the real story, I offer a critical and sympathetic reading of advocates' efforts to move the idea forward. I end by reflecting on whether the political future of restorative justice is better secured by telling the mythical true story or the real story. Key Words restorative justice, conferencing, retributive justice, myths about justice 2 3 Restorative justice: the real story INTRODUCTION Much has been written in recent years that damns and sings the praises of restorative justice. In contrast to the voluminous critical and advocacy literatures, there is a thin empirical record of what is happening on the ground. 1 My aim in this paper is to present the 'real story' ofrestorative justice, one that reflects what has been learned from research on youth justice conferencing 2 in Australia and New Zealand. I am being mostly, although not entirely, ironicin proposing to tell the real story of restorative justice. There are many stories and no real one. I shall recount what I have learned on my journey in the field, which began in the early 1990s (Braithwaite and Daly, 1994) and intensified in 1995 when I moved to Australia to work with restorative justice researchers at the Australian National University and to initiate my own program of research. It has taken me some time to make sense of the idea of restorative justice. Initially, my questions centred on what was happening in the youth justice conference process. What were victims, offenders, and their supporters saying to each other? How did they relate to one another? What did the professionals (the coordinators and police) think was going on? Did the critiques of conferencing, especially from feminist and indigenous perspectives, have merit? I began to observe conferences in 1995; since then, I have observed close to 60 of them; and as part of a major project on conferencing in South Australia, members of my research group and I observed 89 youth justice conferences and interviewed over 170 young people (offenders) and victims associated with them, in 1998 and again, in 1999 (Daly et al., 1998; Daly, 2001b). The more I observed conference processes and listened to those involved in them, attended sessions on restorative justice in professional meetings, and read about restorative justice, the more perplexed I became. I discovered that there was a substantial gap between 4 what I was learning from my research in the field and what the advocates and critics were saying about restorative justice. This moves me to tell the real story, and I do so by analysing four myths that feature in advocates' stories and claims: 1. Restorative justice is the opposite of retributive justice. 2. Restorative justice uses indigenous justice practices and was the dominant form of pre-modern justice. 3. Restorative justice is a 'care' (or feminine) response to crime in comparison to a 'justice' (or masculine) response. 4. Restorative justice can be expected to produce major changes in people. Although I focus on advocates' claims, there can be as much distortion by the critics, as well. Moreover, there are debates among the advocates on the meaning and practice of restorative justice; thus, my characterisation of the advocacy position is meant to show its general emphasis, not to suggest uniformity. I use the concept of myth in two ways. First, myth can be understood simply as a partial truth, a distorted characterisation that requires correction by historical or contemporary evidence. Second, myth can be understood as a special form of narrative. Following Engel (1993: 790-92), myth 'refers not to fantasy or fiction but to a "true story" ... which is sacred, exemplary, significant'. 'The "truth" of myth differs from the "truth" of historical or scientific accounts'. Engel suggests that myths 'differ from other forms of storytelling' in that they 'deal with origins, with birth, with beginnings ... with how something ... began to be'. He discovers in his analysis of the 'origin stories' of parents of children with disabilities that they 'perceive the world in terms of a set of oppositions that originate in the diagnosis of their child' (p. 821). A recurring origin story is that the professional (a doctor) is wrong about the initial diagnosis, and 'the parent's insights have ultimately triumphed over those of the professional' (p. 821). As such, when parents retell their stories, 'the triumphant ending will be achieved 5 again'. 'The very act of retelling is a way to ensure that ... values and outcomes in the myth will triumph over pain, opposition, and disorder'. Engel says that this sense of triumph reveals the 'affirmative, creative power of myth', where myth 'abolishes time' and 'the work of myth [transcends adversity]' (pp. 823-24). When I began this paper, I used the concept of myth as partial truth, a foil against which I could write a more authoritative story. But in analysing the myths, I began to see them in a different light, in Engel's terms, as origin stories that 'encode a set of oppositions' (p. 822). While I shall spend more analytical time telling the real story of restorative justice, using myth as partial truth, I also offer a sympathetic reading of advocates' true story of restorative justice by viewing myth as a creative device to transcend adversity. I end by reflecting on whether the political future of restorative justice is better secured by telling the real story or the mythical true story. THE PROBLEM OF DEFINITION Restorative justice is not easily defined because it encompasses a variety of practices at different stages of the criminal process, including diversion from court prosecution, actions taken in parallel with court decisions, and meetings between victims and offenders at anystage of the criminal process (for example, arrest, pre-sentencing, and prison release). For virtually all legal contexts involving individual criminal matters, restorative justice processes have only been applied to those offenders who have admitted to an offence; as such, it deals with the penalty phase of the criminal process for admitted offenders, not the fact-finding phase. Restorative justice is used not only in adult and juvenile criminal matters, but also in a range of civil matters, including family welfare and child protection, and disputes in schools and workplace settings. Increasingly, one finds the term associated with the resolution of broader political conflicts such as the reconstruction of post-apartheid South Africa (South 6 African Truth and Reconciliation Commission, 1998; Christodoulidis, 2000 for more critical appraisal), post-genocide Rwanda (Drumbl, 2000), and post-sectarian Northern Ireland (Dignan, 2000: 12-13). Given the extraordinarily diverse meanings of the term and the contexts in which it has been applied, it is important for analytical purposes to bound the term to a particular context and set of practices. In this article, I discuss its use in the response to individual crime (as compared to broader political conflict); and in reviewing what is known about restorative justice practices, I focus on studies of youth justice conferencing in Australia and New Zealand, giving particular emphasis to my research in South Australia. Even with a narrowed focus on responses to individual crime, there remain problems of definition. One reason is that because the idea of restorative justice has proved enormously popular with governments, the term is now applied after the fact to programs and policies that have been in place for some time, or it is used to describe reputedly new policing and correctional policies (e.g., LaPrairie, 1999 for Canada; Crawford, 2001 for England and Wales). Until careful empirical work is carried out, we cannot be certain what is going on or the degree to which any of these newer or repackaged practices could be considered 'restorative'. There is great concern among restorative justice advocates to distinguish practices that are near and far from the restorative ideal, and there is debate over how to draw the line on a continuum of practices. One definition, proposed by Marshall (1996: 37), is that restorative justice is 'a process whereby all the parties with a stake in a particular offence come together to resolve collectively how to deal with the aftermath of the offence and its implications for the future'. This definition, which McCold (2000: 358) associates with the 'Purist' model of restorative justice, has been criticised by other restorative justice advocates who say that the definition is too narrow because it includes only face-to-face meetings, it emphasises process over the primary goal of repairing a harm, and actions to repair the harm 7 may need to include coercive responses (Walgrave, 2000: 418). These latter advocates call for a 'Maximalist' model, where restorative justice is defined as 'every action that is primarily oriented towards doing justice by repairing the harm that has been caused by crime' (Bazemore and Walgrave, 1999: 48). In this debate, advocates are considering the uses of restorative justice in youth justice cases only; and yet we continue to see debate and uncertainty over the optimal size of the restorative justice 'tent' and which practices should be included in it. McCold (2000: 401) constructed a venn diagram to distinguish practices that he considers to be fully, mostly, or only partly restorative. He suggests that fully restorative practices occur at the intersection of the three circles of 'victim reparation', 'offender responsibility', and 'communities of care reconciliation'. At that intersection are practices such as peace circles, sentencing circles, and conferences of various types. Outside the intersection are practices he defines as mostly restorative (e.g., truth and reconciliation commissions, victim-offender mediation) or only partly restorative (reparation boards, youth aid panels, victim reparation). The three circles relate to the three major 'stakeholders' in the aftermath of a crime: victims, offenders, and 'communities' (which include victims' and offenders' family members and friends, affected neighbourhoods, and the broader society). Using McCold's diagram, the research reviewed here are of practices associated with a 'fully restorative' model, although as McCold points out (and I concur), this is no guarantee that actual practices are 'restorative'. A selected review of the many lists of 'core elements' of restorative justice (e.g., Dignan, 2000: 4-7; McCold, 2000: 364-72, 399-406; Nova Scotia Department of Justice, 1998: 1-2; Zehr, 1995: 211-12, to name a few) shows these common elements: an emphasis on the role and experience of victims in the criminal process; involvement of all the relevant parties (including the victim, offender, and their supporters) to discuss the offence, its impact, 8 and what should be done to 'repair the harm'; and decision-making carried out by both lay and legal actors. While definitions and lists of core elements of restorative justice vary, all display a remarkable uniformity in defining restorative justice by reference to what it is not, and this is called retributive justice. MYTHS ABOUT RESTORATIVE JUSTICE Myth 1. Restorative justice is the opposite of retributive justice. When one first dips into the restorative justice literature, the first thing one 'learns' is that restorative justice differs sharply from retributive justice. It is said that • restorative justice focuses on repairing the harm caused by crime, whereas retributivejustice focuses on punishing an offence; • restorative justice is characterised by dialogue and negotiation among the parties,whereas retributive justice is characterised by adversarial relations among the parties; and • restorative justice assumes that community members or organisations take a more activerole, whereas for retributive justice, 'the community' is represented by the state. Most striking is that all the elements associated with restorative justice are good, whereas all those associated with retributive justice are bad. The retributive-restorative oppositional contrast is not only made by restorative justice advocates, but increasingly one finds it canonised in criminology and juvenile justice textbooks. The question arises, is it right? On empirical and normative grounds, I suggest that in characterising justice aims and practices, it is neither accurate nor defensible. While I am not alone in taking this position (see Barton, 2000; Duff, 2001; Miller and Blackler, 2000), it is currently held by a small number of us in the field. Despite advocates' well-meaning intentions, the contrast is a highly misleading simplification, which is used to sell the superiority of restorative justice and its set 9 of justice products. To make the sales pitch simple, definite boundaries need to be marked between the good (restorative) and the bad (retributive) justice, to which one might add theugly (rehabilitative) justice. Advocates seem to assume that an ideal justice system should be of one type only, that it should be pure and not contaminated by or mixed with others. 3Before demonstrating the problems with this position, I give a sympathetic reading of what I think advocates are trying to say. Mead's (1917-18) 'The psychology of punitive justice' contrasts two methods of responding to crime. One he termed 'the attitude of hostility toward the lawbreaker' (p. 227), which 'brings with it the attitudes of retribution, repression, and exclusion' (pp. 226-27) and which sees a lawbreaker as 'enemy'. The other, exemplified in the (then) emerging juvenile court, is the 'reconstructive attitude' (p. 234), which tries to 'understand the causes of social and individual breakdown, to mend ... the defective situation', to determine responsibility 'not to place punishment but to obtain future results' (p. 231). Most restorative justice advocates see the justice world through this Meadian lens; they reject the 'attitude of hostility toward the lawbreaker', do not wish to view him or her as 'enemy', and desire an alternative kind of justice. On that score, I concur, as no doubt many other researchers and observers of justice system practices would. However, the 'attitude of hostility' is a caricature of criminal justice, which over the last century and a half has wavered between desires to 'treat' some and 'punish' others, and which surely cannot be encapsulated in the one term, 'retributive justice'. By framing justice aims (or principles) and practices in oppositional terms, restorative justice advocates not only do a disservice to history, they also give a restricted view of the present. They assume that restorative justice practices should exclude elements of retribution; and in rejecting an 'attitude of hostility', they assume that retribution as a justice principle must also be rejected. 10 When observing conferences, I discovered that participants engaged in a flexible incorporation of multiple justice aims, which included: • some elements of retributive justice (that is, censure for past offences),• some elements of rehabilitative justice (for example, by asking, what shall we do toencourage future law-abiding behaviour?), and • some elements of restorative justice (for example, by asking, how can the offender makeup for what he or she did to the victim?). When reporting these findings, one colleague said, 'yes, this is a problem' (Walgrave, personal communication). This speaker's concern was that as restorative justice was being incorporated into the regular justice system, it would turn out to be a set of 'simple techniques', rather than an 'ideal of justice ... in an ideal of society' (Walgrave, 1995: 240, 245) and that its core values would be lost. Another said (paraphrasing), 'retribution may well be present now in conferences, but you wouldn't want to make the argument that it should be present' (Braithwaite, personal communication). These comments provoked me to consider the relationship between restorative and retributive justice, and the role of punishment in restorative justice, in normative terms. Distilling from other papers (e.g., Daly and Immarigeon, 1998: 32-35; Daly, 2000a, 2000b) and arguments by Barton (2000), Duff (1992, 1996, 2001), Hampton (1992, 1998), and Zedner (1994), I have come to see that apparently contrary principles of retribution and reparation should be viewed as dependent on one another. Retributive censure should ideally occur before reparative gestures (or a victim's interest or movement to negotiate these) are possible in an ethical or psychological sense. Both censure and reparation may be experienced as 'punishment' by offenders (even if this is not the intent of decision-makers), and both censure and reparation need to occur before a victim or community can 'reintegrate' an offender into the community. These complex and contingent interactions are expressed in 11 varied ways and should not be viewed as having to follow any one fixed sequence. Moreover, one cannot assume that subsequent actions, such as the victim's forgiving the offender or a reconciliation of a victim and offender (or others), should occur. This may take a long time or never occur. In the advocacy literature, however, I find that there is too quick a move to 'repair the harm', 'heal those injured by crime' or to 're-integrate offenders', passing over a crucial phase of 'holding offenders accountable', which is the retributive part of the process. A major block in communicating ideas about the relationship of retributive to restorative justice is that there is great variability in how people understand and use key terms such as punishment, retribution, and punitiveness. Some argue that incarceration and fines are punishments because they are intended deprivations, whereas probation or a reparative measure such as doing work for a crime victim are not punishment because they are intended to be constructive (Wright, 1991). Others define punishment more broadly to include anything that is unpleasant, a burden, or an imposition of some sort; the intentions of the decision-maker are less significant (Davis, 1992; Duff, 1992, 2001). Some use retribution to describe a justification for punishment (i.e., intended to be in proportion to the harm caused), whereas others use it to describe a form of punishment (i.e., intended to be of a type that is harsh or painful). 4 On proportionality, restorative justice advocates take different positions:some (e.g., Braithwaite and Pettit, 1990) eschew retributivism, favouring instead a freeranging consequentialist justification and highly individualised responses, while others wish to limit restorative justice responses to desert-based, proportionate criteria (Van Ness, 1993; Walgrave and Aertsen, 1996). For the form of punishment, some use retribution in a neutral way to refer to a censuring of harms (e.g., Duff, 1996), whereas most use the term to connote a punitive response, which is associated with emotions of revenge or intentions to inflict pain on wrong-doers (Wright, 1991). The term punitive is rarely defined, no doubt because 12 everyone seems to know what it means. Precisely because this term is used in a commonsensical way by everyone in the field (not just restorative justice scholars), there is confusion over its meaning. Would we say, for example, that any criminal justice sanction is by definition 'punitive', but sanctions can vary across a continuum of greater to lesser punitiveness? Or, would we say that some sanctions are non-punitive and that restorative justice processes aim to maximise the application of non-punitive sanctions? I will not attempt to adjudicate the many competing claims about punishment, retribution, and punitiveness. The sources of antagonism lie not only in varied definitions, but also the different images these definitions conjure in people's heads about justice relations and practices. However, one way to gain some clarity is to conceptualise punishment, retribution, and punitive (and their 'non' counterparts) as separate dimensions, each having its own continuum of meaning, rather than to conflate them, as now typically occurs in the literature. Because the terms 'retributive justice' and 'restorative justice' have such strong meanings and referents, and are used largely by advocates (and others) as metaphors for the bad and the good justice, perhaps they should be jettisoned in analysing current and future justice practices. Instead, we might refer to 'older' and 'newer' modern justice forms. These terms do not provide a content to justice principles or practices, but they do offer a way to depict developments in the justice field with an eye to recent history and with an appreciation that any 'new' justice practices will have many bits of the 'old' in them. 5 The terms alsopermit description and explanation of a larger phenomenon, that is, of a profound transformation of justice forms and practices now occurring in most developed societies in the West, and certainly the English-speaking ones of which I am aware. Restorative justice is only a part of that transformation. By the old justice, I refer to modern practices of courthouse justice, which permit no interaction between victim and offender, where legal actors and other experts do the talking 13 and make decisions, and whose (stated) aim is to punish, or at times, reform an offender. By the new justice, 6 I refer to a variety of recent practices, which normally bring victims andoffenders (and others) together in a process in which both lay and legal actors make decisions, and whose (stated) aim is to repair the harm for victims, offenders, and perhaps other members of 'the community' in ways that matter to them. (While the stated aim of either justice form may be to 'punish the crime' or to 'repair the harm', we should expect to see mixed justice aims in participants' justice talk and practices.) 7 New justice practices areone of several developments in a larger justice field, which also includes the 'new penology' (Feeley and Simon, 1992) and 'unthinkable punishment policies' (Tonry, 1999). The field is fragmented and moving in contradictory directions (Crawford, 1997; Garland, 1996; O'Malley, 1999; Pratt, 2000). Myth 2. Restorative justice uses indigenous justice practices and was the dominant form of pre-modern justice. A common theme in the restorative justice literature is that this reputedly new justice form is 'really not new' (Consedine, 1995: 12). As Consedine puts it, Biblical justice was restorative. So too was justice in most indigenous cultures. In pre-colonial New Zealand, Maori had a fully integrated system of restorative justice ... It was the traditional philosophy of Pacific nations such as Tonga, Fiji and Samoa. ... In pre-Norman Ireland, restorative justice was interwoven ... with the fabric of daily life ... (p. 12). Braithwaite (1999: 1) argues that restorative justice is 'ground[ed] in traditions of justice from the ancient Arab, Greek, and Roman civilisations that accepted a restorative approach even to homicide'. He continues with a large sweep of human history, citing the 'public assemblies ... of the Germanic peoples', 'Indian Hindu [traditions in] 6000-2000 B.C.', and 'ancient 14 Buddhist, Taoist, and Confucian traditions ...'; and he concludes that 'restorative justice has been the dominant model of criminal justice throughout most of human history for all the world's peoples' (p. 1, my emphasis). What an extraordinary claim! Linked with the claim that restorative justice has been the dominant form of criminal justice throughout human history is the claim that present-day indigenous justice practices fall within the restorative justice rubric. Thus, for example, Consedine (1995: 99) says A new paradigm of justice is operating [in New Zealand], which is very traditional in its philosophy, yet revolutionary in its effects. A restorative philosophy of justice has replaced a retributive one. Ironically, 150 years after the traditional Maori restorative praxis was abolished in Aotearoa, youth justice policy is once again operating from the same philosophy. Reverence for and romanticisation of an indigenous past slide over practices that the modern 'civilised' Western mind would object to, such as a variety of harsh physical (bodily) punishments and banishment. At the same time, the modern Western mind may not be able to grasp how certain 'harsh punishments' have been sensible within the terms of a particular culture. Weitekamp (1999: 93) combines 'ancient forms' of justice practice (as restorative) and indigenous groups' current practices (as restorative) when he says that Some of the new[] ... programs are in fact very old. ... [A]ncient forms of restorative justice have been used in [non-state] societies and by early forms of humankind. [F]amily group conferences [and] ... circle hearings [have been used] by indigenous people such as the Aboriginals, the Inuit, and the native Indians of North and South America. ... It is kind of ironic that we have at [the turn of this century] to go back to methods and forms of conflict resolution which were practiced some millennia ago by our ancestors ... 15 I confess to a limited knowledge of justice practices and systems throughout the history of humankind. What I know is confined mainly to the past three centuries and to developments in the United States and several other countries. Thus, in addressing this myth, I do so from a position of ignorance in knowing only a small portion of history. Upon reflection, however, my lack of historical knowledge may not matter. All that is required is the realisation that advocates do not intend to write authoritative histories of justice. Rather, they are constructing origin myths about restorative justice. If the first form of human justice was restorative justice, then advocates can claim a need to recover it from a history of 'takeover' by state-sponsored retributive justice. And, by identifying current indigenous practices as restorative justice, advocates can claim a need to recover these practices from a history of 'takeover' by white colonial powers that instituted retributive justice. Thus, the history of justice practices is re-written by advocates not only to authorise restorative justice as the first human form of justice, but also to argue that it is congenial with modern-day indigenous and, as we shall see in Myth 3, feminist social movements for justice. In the restorative justice field, most commentators focus specifically (and narrowly) on changes that occurred over a 400-year period (8th to 11th centuries) in England (and some European countries), where a system of largely kin-based dispute settlement gave way to a court system, in which feudal lords retained a portion of property forfeited by an offender. In England, this loose system was centralised and consolidated during the century following the Norman Invasion in 1066, as the development of state (crown) law depended on the collection of revenues collected by judges for the king. For restorative justice advocates, the transformation of disputes as offences between individuals to offences against the state is one element that marked the end of pre-modern forms of restorative justice. A second element is the decline in compensation to the victim for the losses from a crime (Weitekamp, 1999). 16 Advocates' constructions of the history of restorative justice, that is, the origin myth that a superior justice form prevailed before the imposition of retributive justice, is linked to their desire to maintain a strong oppositional contrast between retributive and restorative justice. That is to say, the origin myth and oppositional contrast are both required in telling the true story of restorative justice. I do not see bad faith at work here. Rather, advocates are trying to move an idea into the political and policy arena, and this may necessitate having to utilise a simple contrast of the good and the bad justice, along with an origin myth of how it all came to be. What does concern me is that the specific histories and practices of justice in premodern societies are smoothed over and a lumped together as one justice form. Is it appropriate to refer to all of these justice practices as 'restorative'? No, I think not. What do these justice practices in fact have in common? What is gained, and more importantly, what is lost by this homogenising move? Efforts to write histories of restorative justice, where a pre-modern past is romantically (and selectively) invoked to justify a current justice practice, are not only in error, but also unwittingly reinscribe an ethnocentrism their authors wish to avoid. As Blagg (1997) and Cain (2000) point out, there has been an orientalist appropriation of indigenous justice practices, largely in the service of strengthening advocates' positions. A common, albeit erroneous, claim is that the modern idea of conferencing 'has its direct roots in Maori culture' (Shearing, 2001: 218, note 5; see also Consedine, 1995). The real story is that conferencing emerged in the 1980s, in the context of Maori political challenges to white New Zealanders and to their welfare and criminal justice systems. Investing decision-making practices with Maori cultural values meant that family groups (whanau) should have a greater say in what happens, that venues should be culturally appropriate, and that processes should accommodate a mix of culturally appropriate practices. New Zealand's minority group population includes not only the Maori but also Pacific Island 17 Polynesians. Therefore, with the introduction of conferencing, came awareness of the need to incorporate different elements of 'cultural appropriateness' into the conference process. But the devising of a (white, bureaucratic) justice practice that is flexible and accommodating toward cultural differences does not mean that conferencing is an indigenous justice practice. Maxwell and Morris (1993: 4), who know the New Zealand situation well, are clear on this point: A distinction must be drawn between a system, which attempts to re-establish the indigenous model of pre-European times, and a system of justice, which is culturally appropriate. The New Zealand system is an attempt to establish the latter, not to replicate the former. As such, it seeks to incorporate many of the features apparent in whanau decision-making processes and seen in meetings on marae today, but it also contains elements quite alien to indigenous models. Conferencing is better understood as a fragmented justice form: it splices white, bureaucratic forms of justice with elements of informal justice that may include non-white (or non-Western) values or methods of judgment, with all the attendant dangers of such 'spliced justice' (Blagg, 1997, 1998; Daly, 1998; Findlay, 2000; Pavlich, 1996). With the flexibility of informal justice, practitioners, advocates, and members of minority groups may see the potential for introducing culturally sensible and responsive forms of justice. But to say that conferencing is an indigenous justice practice (or 'has its roots in indigenous justice') is to reengage a white-centred view of the world. As Blagg (1998: 12) asks rhetorically, 'Are we once again creaming off the cultural value of people simply to suit our own nostalgia in this age of pessimism and melancholia'? A good deal of the advocacy literature is of this ilk: white-centred, creaming off, and homogenising of cultural difference and specificity. 18 Myth 3. Restorative justice is a 'care' (or feminine) response to crime in comparison to a 'justice' (or masculine) response. Myths 2 and 3 have a similar oppositional logic, but play with different dichotomies. The following chart shows the terms that are often linked to restorative and retributive justice. restorative justice retributive justice pre-modern modern indigenous (informal) state (formal) feminine (care) masculine (justice) eastern (Japan) western (US) superior justice inferior justice Note the power inversion, essential to the origin myth of restorative justice, where the subordinated or marginalised groups (pre-modern, indigenous, eastern, and feminine) are aligned with the more superior justice form. Many readers will be familiar with the 'care' and 'justice' dichotomy. It was put forward by Gilligan in her popular book, In a Different Voice (1982). For about a decade, it seemed that most feminist legal theory articles were organised around the 'different voice' versus 'male dominance' perspectives of Gilligan and MacKinnon (1987), respectively. In criminology, Heidensohn (1986) and Harris (1987) attempted to apply the care/justice dichotomy to the criminal justice system. Care responses to crime are depicted as personalised and as based on a concrete and active morality, whereas justice responses are depicted as depersonalised, based on rights and rules, and a universalising and abstract morality. Care responses are associated with the different (female) voice, and these are distinguished from justice responses, which are associated with the general (if male) voice. In her early work, Gilligan argued that both voices should have equal importance in moral reasoning, but women's voices were misheard or judged as morally inferior to men's. A 19 critical literature developed rapidly, and Gilligan began to reformulate and clarify her argument. She recognised that 'care' responses in a 'justice' framework left 'the basic assumptions of a justice framework intact ... and that as a moral perspective, care [was] less well elaborated' (Gilligan, 1987: 24). At the time, the elements that Gilligan associated with a care response to crime were contextual and relational reasoning, and individualised responses made by decision-makers who were not detached from the conflict (or crime). In 1989, I came into the debate, arguing that we should challenge the association of justice and care reasoning with male/masculine and female/feminine voices, respectively (Daly, 1989). I suggested that this gender-linked association was not accurate empirically, and I argued that it would be misleading to think that an alternative to men's forms of criminal law and justice practices could be found by adding women's voice or reconstituting the system along the lines of an ethic of care. I viewed the care/justice dichotomy as recapitulating centuries long debates in modern Western criminology and legal philosophy over the aims and purposes of punishment, e.g., deterrence and retribution or rehabilitation, and uniform or individualised responses. Further, I noted that although the dichotomy depicted different ideological emphases in the response to crime since the nineteenth century, the relational and concrete reasoning that Gilligan associated with the female voice was how in fact the criminal law is interpreted and applied. It is the voice of criminal justice practices. The problem, then, was not that the female voice was absent in criminal court practices, but rather that certain relations were presupposed, maintained, and reproduced. Feminist analyses of law and criminal justice centre on the androcentric (some would argue, phallocentric) character of these relations for what comes to be understood as 'crime', for the meanings of 'consent', and for punishment (for cogent reviews, see Coombs, 1995; Smart, 1989, 1992). While feminist scholars continue to emphasise the need to bring women's experiences and 'voices' into the criminological and legal frame, this is not the same thing as arguing that there is a universal 20 'female voice' in moral reasoning. During the late 1980s and 1990s, feminist arguments moved decisively beyond dichotomous and essentialist readings of sex/gender in analysing relations of power and 'difference' in law and justice. Gilligan's different voice construct, though novel and important at the time, has been superseded by more complex and contingent analyses of ethics and morality. But the different voice is back, and unfortunately, the authors who are using it seem totally unaware of key shifts in feminist thinking. We see now that the 'ethic of care' (Persephone) is pitched as the alternative to retributive justice (Portia). One example is a recent paper by Masters and Smith (1998), who attempt to demonstrate that Persephone, the voice of caring, is evident in a variety of restorative responses to crime. Their arguments confuse, however, because they argue that Persephone is 'informed by an ethic of care as well as an ethic of justice' (p. 11). And toward the end of the article, they say 'we cannot do without Portia (ethic of justice), but neither can we do without Persephone' (p. 21). Thus, it is not clear whether, within the terms of their argument, Persephone stands for the feminine or includes both the masculine and feminine, or whether we need both Portia and Persephone. They apparently agree with all three positions. They also see little difference between a 'feminine' and a 'feminist approach', terms that they use interchangeably. In general, they normally credit 'relational justice as a distinctly feminine approach to crime and conflict' (p. 13). They say that 'reintegrative shaming can be considered a feminine (or Persephone) theory' and that there is a 'fit between reintegrative shaming practice and the feminist ethic of care' (p. 13, my italics since the authors have shifted from a feminine ethic to a feminist ethic). Toward the end of the paper, they make the astonishing claim, one that I suspect my colleague John Braithwaite would find difficult to accept, that 'reintegrative shaming is perhaps the first feminist criminological theory'. They argue this is so because the 'practice of 21 reintegrative shaming can be interpreted as being grounded in a feminine, rather than a masculine understanding of the social world' (p. 20). There is a lot to unpick here, and I shall not go point by point. Nor do I wish to undermine the spirit of the paper since the authors' intentions are laudable, in particular, their desire to define a more progressive way to respond to crime. My concern is that using simple gender dichotomies, or any dichotomies for that matter, to describe principles and practices of justice will always fail us, will always lead to great disappointment. 8 Traditionalcourthouse justice works with the abstraction of criminal law, but must deal with the messy world of people's lives, and hence, must deal with context and relations. 'Care' responses to some offenders can re-victimise some victims; they may be helpful in some cases or for someoffenders or for some victims or they may also be oppressive and unjust for other offenders and victims. Likewise, with so-called 'justice' responses. The set of terms lined up along the 'male/masculine' and 'female/feminine' poles is long and varied: some terms are about process, others with modes of response (e.g., repair the harm), and still others, with ways of thinking about culpability for the harm. I am struck by the frequency with which people use dichotomies such as the male and female voice, retributive and restorative justice, or West and East, to depict justice principles and practices. Such dichotomies are also used to construct normative positions about justice, where it is assumed (I think wrongly) that the sensibility of one side of the dualism necessarily excludes (or is antithetical to) the sensibility of the other. Increasingly, scholars are coming to see the value of theorising justice in hybrid terms, of seeing connections and contingent relations between apparent oppositions (see e.g., Bottoms, 1998; Daly, 2000a; Duff, 2001; Hudson, 1998; Zedner, 1994). Like the advocates promoting Myth 2, those promoting Myth 3 want to emphasise the importance of identifying a different response to crime than the one currently in use. I am 22 certainly on the side of that aspiration. However, I cannot agree with the terms in which the position has been argued and sold to academic audiences and wider publics. There is a loss of credibility when analyses do not move beyond oppositional justice metaphors, when claims are imprecise, and when extraordinary tales of repair and goodwill are assumed to be typical of the restorative justice experience. Myth 4. Restorative justice can be expected to produce major changes in people. I have said that attention needs to be given to the reality on the ground, to what is actually happening in, and resulting from, practices that fall within the rubric of restorative justice. There are several levels to describe and analyse what is going on: first, what occurs in the justice practice itself; second, the relationship between this and broader system effects; and third, how restorative justice is located in the broader politics of crime control. I focus on the first level and present two forms of evidence: (1) stories of dramatic transformations or moving accounts of reconciliation and (2) aggregated information across a larger number of cases, drawing from research on conference observations and interviews with participants. Several reviewers of this paper took issue with Myth 4, saying that 'advocates are less likely to claim changes in people' or that 'there is no real evidence that restorative justice of itself can be expected to produce major changes in people'. Although I am open to empirical inquiry, my reading of the advocacy literature from the United States, Canada, Australia, and New Zealand suggests that Myth 4 is prevalent. It is exemplified by advocates' stories of how people are transformed or by their general assertions of the benefits of restorative justice. For example, McCold (2000: 359, 363) reports that 'facilitators of restorative processes regularly observe a personal and social transformation occur during the course of the process' and 'we now have a growing body of research on programs that everyone agrees are truly restorative, clearly demonstrating their remarkable success at healing and 23 conciliation'. McCold gives no citations to the research literature. While 'personal and social transformation' undoubtedly occurs some of the time, and is likely to be rare in a courtroom proceeding, advocates lead us to think that it is typical in a restorative justice process. This is accomplished by telling a moving story, which is then used to stand as a generalisation. Stories of restorative justice Consedine (1995: 9) opens his book by excerpting from a 1993 New Zealand news story: The families of two South Auckland boys killed by a car welcomed the accused driver yesterday with open arms and forgiveness. The young man, who gave himself up to the police yesterday morning, apologised to the families and was ceremonially reunited with the Tongan and Samoan communities at a special service last night. ... The 20-year old Samoan visited the Tongan families after his court appearance to apologise for the deaths of the two children in Mangere. The Tongan and Samoan communities of Mangere later gathered at the Tongan Methodist Church in a service of reconciliation. The young man sat at the feast table flanked by the mothers of the dead boys. Consedine says that this case provides 'ample evidence of the power that healing and forgiveness can play in our daily lives. ... The grieving Tongan and Samoan communities simply embraced the young driver ... and forgave him. His deep shame, his fear, his sorrow, his alienation from the community was resolved' (p. 162). Another example comes from Umbreit (1994: 1). His book opens with the story of Linda and Bob Jackson, whose house was broken into; they subsequently met with the offender as part of the offender's sentence disposition. The offender, Allan, 'felt better after the mediation ... he was able to make amends to the Jacksons'. Moreover, 'Linda and Bob felt less vulnerable, were able to sleep better and received payment for their losses. All parties 24 were able to put this event behind them'. Later in the book, Umbreit (1994: 197-202) offers another case study of a second couple, Bob and Anne, after their house was burglarised a second time. He summarises the outcome this way: Bob, Anne, and Jim [the offender] felt the mediation process and outcome was fair. All were very satisfied with participation in the program. Rather than playing passive roles ... [they] actively participated in 'making things right'. During a subsequent conversation with Bob, he commented that 'this was the first time (after several victimisations) that I ever felt any sense of fairness. The courts always ignored me before. They didn't care about my concerns. And Jim isn't such a bad kid after all, was he?' Jim also indicated that he felt better after the mediation and more aware of the impact the burglary had on Bob and Anne (p. 202). Lastly, there is the fable of Sam, an adolescent offender who attended a diversionary conference, which was first related by Braithwaite (1996) and retold by Shearing (2001: 214- 215). Braithwaite (1996: 9) says that his story is a 'composite of several Sams I have seen'; thus, while he admits that it is not a real story of Sam, it is said to show the 'essential features ... of restorative justice' (Shearing, 2001: 214). This is something like a building contractor saying to a potential home buyer, 'this is a composite of the house I can build for you; it's not the real house, but it's like many houses I have sold to happy buyers over the years'. What the composite gives and what the building contractor offers us is a vision of the possible, of the perfect house. Whether the house can ever be built is less important than imagining its possibility and its perfection. This is the cornerstone of the true story of restorative justice, like many proposed justice innovations of the past. Sam's story, as told by Braithwaite, is longer than I give here, and thus, I leave out emotional details that make any story compelling. Sam, who is homeless and says his parents abused him, has no one who really cares about him except his older sister, his former hockey 25 coach at school, and his Uncle George. These people attend the conference, along with the elderly female victim and her daughter. Sam says he knocked over the victim and took her purse because he needed the money. His significant others rebuke him for doing this, but also remember that he had a good side before he started getting into trouble. The victim and daughter describe the effects of the robbery, but Sam does not seem to be affected. After his apparent callous response to the victim, Sam's sister cries, and during a break, she reveals that she too had been abused by their parents. When the conference reconvenes, Sam's sister speaks directly to Sam, and without mentioning details, says she understands what Sam went through. The victim appreciates what is being said and begins to cry. Sam's callous exterior begins to crumble. He says he wants to do something for the victim, but doesn't know what he can do without a home or job. His sister offers her place for him to stay, and the coach says he can offer him some work. At the end of the conference, the victim hugs Sam and tearfully says good luck, Sam apologises again, and Uncle George says he will continue to help Sam and his sister when needed. Many questions arise in reading stories like these. How often do expressions of kindness and understanding, of movement toward repair and goodwill, actually occur? What are the typical 'effects' on participants? Is the perfect house of restorative justice ever built? Another kind of evidence, aggregated data across a larger number of cases, can provide some answers. Statistical aggregates of restorative justice Here are some highlights of what has been learned from research on youth justice conferences in Australia and New Zealand. 9 Official data show that about 85 to 90 percent ofconferences resulted in agreed outcomes, and 80 percent of young people completed their agreements. From New Zealand research in the early 1990s (Maxwell and Morris, 1993), 26 conferences appeared to be largely offender-centred events. In 51 percent of the 146 cases where a victim was identified, did the victim attend the conference (p. 118). Of all the victims interviewed who attended a conference (sometimes there were multiple victims), 25 percent said they felt worse as a result of the conference (p. 119). Negative feelings were linked to being dissatisfied with the conference outcome, which was judged to be too lenient toward the offender. Of all those interviewed (offenders, their supporters, and victims) victims were the least satisfied with the outcome of the family conference: 49 percent said they were satisfied (p. 120) compared with 84 percent of young people and 85 percent of parents (p. 115). Maxwell and Morris report that 'monitoring of [conference] outcomes was generally poor' (p. 123), and while they could not give precise percentages, it appeared that 'few [victims] had been informed of the eventual success or otherwise of the outcome' and that this 'was a source of considerable anger for them' (p. 123). Elsewhere, Maxwell and Morris (1996:95-96) report that 'the new system remains largely unresponsive to cultural differences' in handling Maori cases, which they argue is a consequence, in part, of too few resources. The most robust finding across all the studies in the region (see review in Daly, 2001a) is that conferences receive very high marks along dimensions of procedural justice, that is, victims and offenders view the process and the outcomes as fair. In the Re- Integrative Shaming Experiments (RISE) in Canberra, admitted offenders were randomly assigned to court and conference. Strang et al. (1999) have reported results from the RISE project on their website by showing many pages of percentages for each variable for each of the four offences in the experiment (violent, property, shoplifting, and drink driving). They have summarised this mass of numbers in a set of comparative statements without attaching their claims to percentages. Here is what they report. Compared to those offenders who went to court, those going to conferences have higher levels of procedural justice, higher levels of 27 restorative justice, and an increased respect for the police and law. Compared to victims whose cases went to court, conference victims have higher levels of recovery from the offence. Conference victims also had high levels of procedural justice, but they could not be compared to court victims, who rarely attended court proceedings. These summary statements are the tip of the RISE iceberg. In a detailed analysis of the RISE website results, Kurki (2001) finds offence-based differences in the court and conference experiences of RISE participants, and she notes that RISE researchers' reports of claimed court and conference differences are not uniform across offence types. Like other studies, the South Australia Juvenile Justice (SAJJ) Research on Conferencing Project finds very high levels of procedural justice registered by offenders and victims at conferences. To items such as, were you treated fairly, were you treated with respect, did you have a say in the agreement, among others, 80 to 95 percent of victims and offenders said that they were treated fairly and had a say. In light of the procedural justice literature (Tyler, 1990; Tyler et al., 1997), these findings are important. Procedural justice scholars argue that when citizens perceive a legal process as fair, when they are listened to and treated with respect, there is an affirmation of the legitimacy of the legal order. Compared to the high levels of perceived procedural justice, the SAJJ project finds relatively less evidence of restorativeness. The measures of restorativeness tapped the degree to which offenders and victims recognised the other and were affected by the other; they focused on the degree to which there was positive movement between the offender and victim and their supporters during the conference (the SAJJ measures are more concrete and relational measures of restorativeness than those used in RISE). Whereas very high proportions of victims and offenders (80 to 95 percent) said that the process was fair (among other variables tapping procedural justice), 'restorativeness' was evident in 30 to 50 percent of conferences (depending on the item), and solidly in no more than about one-third. Thus, in 28 this jurisdiction where conferences are used routinely, 10 fairness can more easily be achievedthan restorativeness. As but one example, from the interviews we learned that from the victims' perspectives, less than 30 percent of offenders were perceived as making genuine apologies, but from the offenders' perspectives, close to 60 percent said their apology was genuine. The SAJJ results lead me to think that young people (offenders) and victims orient themselves to a conference and what they hope to achieve in it in ways different that the advocacy literature imagines. The stance of empathy and openness to 'the other', the expectation of being able to speak and reflect on one's actions, and the presence of new justice norms (or language) emphasising repair -- all of these are novel cultural elements for most participants. Young people appear to be as, if not more, interested in repairing their own reputations than in repairing the harm to victims. Among the most important things that the victims hoped would occur at the conference was for the offender to hear how the offence affected them, but half the offenders told us that the victim's story had no effect or only a little effect on them. How often, then, does the exceptional or 'nirvana' story of repair and goodwill occur? I devised a measure that combined the SAJJ observer's judgment of the degree to which a conference 'ended on a high, a positive note of repair and good will' with one that rated the conference on a 5-point scale from poor to exceptional. While the first tapped the degree to which there was movement between victims, offenders, and their supporters toward each other, the second tapped a more general feeling about the conference dynamics and how well the conference was managed by the coordinator. With this combined measure, 10 percent of conferences were rated very highly, another 40 percent, good; and the rest, a mixed, fair, or poor rating. If conferencing is used routinely (not just in a select set of cases), I suspect that 29 the story of Sam and Uncle George will be infrequent; it may happen 10 percent of the time, if that. Assessing the 'effects' of conferences on participants is complex because such effects change over time and, for victims, they are contingent on whether offenders come through on promises made, as we learned from New Zealand research. I present findings on victims' sense of having recovered from the offence and on young people's re-offending in the postconference period. In the Year 2 (1999) interviews with victims, over 60 percent said they had 'fully recovered' from the offence, that it was 'all behind' them. Their recovery was more likely when offenders completed the agreement than when they did not, but recovery was influenced by a mixture of elements: the conference process, support from family and friends, the passage of time, and personal resources such as their own resilience. The SAJJ project finds that conferences can have positive effects on reducing victims' anger toward and fear of offenders. Drawing from the victim interviews in 1998 and 1999, over 75 percent of victims felt angry toward the offender before the conference, but this dropped to 44 percent after the conference and was 39 percent a year later. Close to 40 percent of victims were frightened of the offender before the conference, but this dropped to 25 percent after the conference and was 18 percent a year later. Therefore, for victims, meeting offenders in the conference setting can have beneficial results. The conference effect everyone asks about is, does it reduce re-offending? Proof (or disproof) of reductions in re-offending from conferences (compared not only to court, but to other interventions such as formal caution, other diversion approaches, or no legal action at all) will not be available for a long time, if ever. The honest answer to the re-offending question is 'we'll probably never know' because the amounts of money would be exorbitant and research methods using experimental designs judged too risky in an ethical and political sense. 30 To date, there have been three studies of conferencing and re-offending in Australia and New Zealand, one of which compares re-offending for a sample of offenders randomly assigned to conference and court and two that explore whether re-offending can be linked to things that occur in conferences. 11 The RISE project finds that for one of four major offencecategories studied (violent offences compared to drink driving, property offences, shoplifting), those offenders who were assigned to a conference had a significantly reduced rate of re-offending than those who were assigned to court (Sherman, Strang, and Woods, 2000). As others have said (Abel, 1982: 278; Levrant et al., 1999: 17-22), there is a great faith placed on the conference process to change young offenders, when the conditions of their day to day lives, which may be conducive to getting into trouble, may not change at all. The SAJJ project asked if there were things that occurred in conferences that could predict reoffending, over and above those variables known to be conducive to lawbreaking (and its detection): past offending and social marginality (Hayes and Daly, 2001). In a regression analysis with a simultaneous inclusion of variables, we found that over and above the young person's race-ethnicity (Aboriginal or non-Aboriginal), sex, whether s/he offended prior to the offence that led to the SAJJ conference, and a measure of the young person's mobility and marginality, there were two conference elements associated with re-offending. When young people were observed to be mostly or fully remorseful and when outcomes were achieved by genuine consensus, they were less likely to re-offend during an 8- to 12-month period after the conference. These results are remarkably similar to those of Maxwell and Morris (2000) in their study of re-offending in New Zealand. They found that what happens in conferences (e.g., a young person's expressions of remorse and agreeing [or not] with the outcome, among other variables) could distinguish those young people who were and were not 'persistently reconvicted' during a 6-1/2 year follow up period. 31 THE REAL OR THE TRUE STORY? Advocates want to tell a particular kind of story, the mythical true story of restorative justice. This story asks people to develop their 'caring' sides and to 'resist tyranny with compassion' (Braithwaite, 1999: 2). It suggests that amidst adversity, there is great potential 'for doing good' for self and others (Braithwaite, 1999: 2, paraphrasing Eckel, 1997). It rewrites the history of justice practices by celebrating a return to pre-modern forms, and it re-colonises indigenous practices by identifying them as exemplars of restorative justice. The true story offers some hope, not only for a better way to do justice, but also for strengthening mechanisms of informal social control, and consequently, to minimise reliance on formal social control, the machinery and institutions of criminal justice. In order to sell the idea of restorative justice to a wide audience, advocates have painted a dichotomous, oppositional picture of different justice forms, with restorative justice trumping retributive justice as the superior one. There is a certain appeal to this framing of justice: it offers two choices, and it tells us which side is right. With this framing, who could possibly be on the side of retribution and retributive justice? Only the bad guys, of course. When we move from the metaphors and slogans to the hard work of establishing the philosophical, legal, and organisational bases of this idea, and of documenting what actually occurs in these practices, the true story fails us. It lets us down because simple oppositional dualisms are inadequate in depicting criminal justice, even an ideal justice system. With respect to youth justice conferencing, extraordinary tales of repair and goodwill may occur, but we should not expect them to occur as frequently as the advocates would have us think. The real story of restorative justice is a more qualified one. Empirical evidence of conferencing in Australia and New Zealand suggests that very high proportions of people find the process fair; on many measures of procedural justice, it succeeds. However, I am finding from the SAJJ project that it is relatively more difficult for victims and offenders to 32 find common ground and to hear each other's stories, or for offenders to give sincere apologies and victims to understand that apologies are sincere. There appear to be limits on 'repairing the harm' for offenders and victims, in part because the idea is novel and unfamiliar for most ordinary citizens. For youthful lawbreakers, the limits also inhere in the salience of any legal process or adult exhortations to 'stay out of trouble', and the problems that adolescents may have in 'recognising the other', an empathetic orientation that is assumed to be central to a restorative process. For victims, the limits reside in the capacity to be generous to lawbreakers and to see lawbreakers as capable of change. A variety of observational and interview items from the SAJJ project suggests that a minority of conferences have the necessary raw material for restorativeness to occur. (One needs to be careful in generalising: the frequency of restorativeness would depend greatly on whether a jurisdiction uses conferences selectively or routinely and what kinds of cases are in the sample, that is, the mix of violence and property, the degree of seriousness, and victimoffender relations.) Overall, the real story of restorative justice has many positives and has much to commend, but the evidence is mixed. Conferencing, or any new justice practice, is not nirvana and ought not to be sold in those terms. In the political arena, telling the mythical true story of restorative justice may be an effective means of reforming parts of the justice system. It may inspire legislatures to pass new laws and it may provide openings to experiment with alternative justice forms. All of this can be a good thing. Perhaps, in fact, the politics of selling justice ideas may require people to tell mythical true stories. The real story attends to the murk and constraints of justice organisations, of people's experiences as offenders and victims and their capacities and desires to 'repair the harm'. It reveals a picture that is less sharp-edged and more equivocal. My reading of the evidence is that face-to-face encounters between victims and offenders and their supporters is a practice worth maintaining, and perhaps enlarging, 33 although we should not expect it to deliver strong stories of repair and goodwill most of the time. If we want to avoid the cycle of optimism and pessimism (Matthews, 1988) that so often attaches to any justice innovation, then we should be courageous and tell the real story of restorative justice. But, in telling the real story, there is some risk that a promising, fledgling idea will meet a premature death. 34 References Abel, Richard L. (1982) 'The contradictions of informal justice', in R. L. Abel (ed.) The Politics of Informal Justice, vol. 1, pp. 267-320. New York: Academic Press. Ashworth, Andrew (1993) 'Some doubts about restorative justice', Criminal Law Forum 4: 277-99. Bargen, Jenny (1996) 'Kids, cops, courts, conferencing and children's rights: a note on perspectives', Australian Journal of Human Rights 2(2): 209-28. Barton, Charles (2000) 'Empowerment and retribution in criminal justice', in H. Strang and J. Braithwaite (eds.) Restorative Justice: Philosophy to Practice, pp. 55-76. Aldershot: Ashgate/Dartmouth. Bazemore, Gordon and Mara Schiff (eds.) (2001) Restorative Community Justice. Cincinnati: Anderson Publishing. Bazemore, Gordon and Lode Walgrave (1999) 'Restorative juvenile justice: in search of fundamentals and an outline for systemic reform', in G. Bazemore and L. Walgrave (eds.) Restorative Juvenile Justice: Repairing the Harm of Youth Crime, pp. 45-74. Monsey, NY: Criminal Justice Press. Blagg, Harry (1997) 'A just measure of shame? Aboriginal youth and conferencing in Australia', British Journal of Criminology 37(4): 481-501. Blagg, Harry (1998) 'Restorative visions and restorative justice practices: conferencing, ceremony and reconciliation in Australia', Current Issues in Criminal Justice 10(1): 5- 14. Bottoms, Anthony E. (1998) 'Five puzzles in von Hirsch's theory of punishment', in A. Ashworth and M. Wasik (eds.) Fundamentals of Sentencing Theory: Essays in Honour of Andrew von Hirsch, pp. 53-100. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Braithwaite, John (1996) 'Restorative justice and a better future', Dorothy J. Killam Memorial 35 Lecture, reprinted in Dalhousie Review 76(1): 9-32. Braithwaite, John (1999) 'Restorative justice: assessing optimistic and pessimistic accounts', in M. Tonry (ed.) Crime and Justice: A Review of Research 25: 1-127. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Braithwaite, John and Kathleen Daly (1994) 'Masculinities, violence and communitarian control', in T. Newburn and E. A. Stanko (eds.) Just Boys Doing Business?, pp. 189- 213. New York: Routledge. Braithwaite, John and Phillip Pettit (1990) Not Just Deserts: A Republican Theory of Criminal Justice. New York: Oxford. Cain, Maureen (2000) 'Orientalism, occidentalism and the sociology of crime', British Journal of Criminology 40(2): 239-60. Christodoulidis, Emilios (2000) '"Truth and reconciliation" as risks', Social & Legal Studies 9(2): 179-204. Coombs, Mary (1995) 'Putting women first', Michigan Law Review 93(6): 1686-1712. Consedine, Jim (1995) Restorative Justice: Healing the Effects of Crime. Lyttelton, New Zealand: Ploughshares Publications. Cottingham, John (1979) 'Varieties of retribution', Philosophical Quarterly 29: 238-46. Crawford, Adam (1997) The Local Governance of Crime: Appeals to Community and Partnerships. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Crawford, Adam (2001) 'The prospects for restorative youth justice in England and Wales: a tale of two acts', in K. McEvoy and T. Newburn (eds.) Criminology and Conflict Resolution, forthcoming. London: Macmillan. Crawford, Adam and Jo Goodey (eds.) (2000) Integrating a Victim Perspective within Criminal Justice. Aldershot: Ashgate/Dartmouth. Daly, Kathleen (1989) 'Criminal justice ideologies and practices in different voices: some 36 feminist questions about justice', International Journal of the Sociology of Law 17(1): 1-18. Daly, Kathleen (1998) 'Restorative justice: moving past the caricatures', Paper presented to Seminar on Restorative Justice, Institute of Criminology, University of Sydney Law School, Sydney, April. <http://www.gu.edu.au/school/ccj/kdaly.html> Daly, Kathleen (2000a) 'Revisiting the relationship between retributive and restorative justice', in H. Strang and J. Braithwaite (eds.) Restorative Justice: Philosophy to Practice, pp. 33-54. Aldershot: Ashgate/Dartmouth. Daly, Kathleen (2000b) 'Sexual assault and restorative justice', paper presented to Restorative Justice and Family Violence Conference, Australian National University, Canberra, July. <http://www.gu.edu.au/school/ccj/kdaly.html> Daly, Kathleen (2001a) 'Conferencing in Australia and New Zealand: variations, research findings, and prospects', in A. Morris and G. Maxwell (eds.) Restorative Justice for Juveniles: Conferencing, Mediation and Circles, pp. 59-84. Oxford: Hart Publishing Ltd. <http://www.gu.edu.au/school/ccj/kdaly.html> Daly, Kathleen (2001b) South Australia Juvenile Justice (SAJJ) Research on Conferencing,Technical Report No. 2: Research Instruments in Year 2 (1999) and Background Notes. School of Criminology and Criminal Justice, Griffith University, Brisbane, Queensland. <http://www.aic.gov.au/rjustice/sajj/index.html> Daly, Kathleen and Hennessey Hayes (2001) 'Restorative justice and conferencing in Australia', Trends & Issues in Crime and Criminal Justice No. 186. Canberra: Australian Institute of Criminology. <http://www.aic.gov.au/publications/tandi/tandi186.html> Daly, Kathleen and Russ Immarigeon (1998) 'The past, present, and future of restorative justice: some critical reflections', Contemporary Justice Review 1(1): 21-45. 37 Daly, Kathleen, Michele Venables, Mary McKenna, Liz Mumford, and Jane Christie- Johnston (1998) South Australia Juvenile Justice (SAJJ) Research on Conferencing, Technical Report No. 1: Project Overview and Research Instruments (Year 1), School of Criminology and Criminal Justice, Griffith University, Brisbane, Queensland. <http://www.aic.gov.au/rjustice/sajj/index.html> Davis, Gwynn (1992) Making Amends: Mediation and Reparation in Criminal Justice. London: Routledge. Delgado, Richard (2000) 'Prosecuting violence: a colloquy on race, community, and justice', Stanford Law Review 52: 751-74. Dignan, Jim (2000) Restorative Justice Options for Northern Ireland: A Comparative Review. Belfast: The Stationery Office Bookshop. Drumbl, Mark A. (2000) 'Retributive justice and the Rwandan genocide', Punishment & Society 2(3): 287-308. Duff, R. Antony (1992) 'Alternatives to punishment -- or alternative punishments?', in W. Cragg (ed.) Retributivism and Its Critics, pp. 44-68. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner. Duff, R. Antony (1996) 'Penal communications: recent work in the philosophy of punishment', in M. Tonry (ed.) Crime and Justice: A Review of Research 20: 1-97. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Duff, R. Antony (2001) 'Restoration and retribution', Paper presented to Cambridge Seminar on Restorative Justice, Toronto, May. Engel, David (1993) 'Origin myths; narratives of authority, resistance, disability, and law', Law & Society Review 27(4): 785-826. Feeley, Malcolm and Jonathan Simon (1992) 'The new penology; notes on the emerging strategy of corrections and its implications', Criminology 30(4): 449-74. Findlay, Mark (2000) 'Decolonising restoration and justice in transitional cultures' in H. 38 Strang and J. Braithwaite (eds.) Restorative Justice: Philosophy to Practice, pp. 185- 201. Aldershot: Ashgate/Dartmouth. Garland, David (1996) 'The limits of the sovereign state', British Journal of Criminology 36(4): 445-71. Gilligan, Carol (1982) In a Different Voice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Gilligan, Carol (1987) 'Moral orientation and moral development', in E. Kittay and D. Meyers (eds.) Women and Moral Theory, pp. 19-33. Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Littlefield. Hampton, Jean (1992) 'Correcting harms versus righting wrongs: the goal of retribution', UCLA Law Review 39: 1659-1702. Hampton, Jean (1998) 'Punishment, feminism, and political identity: a case study in the expressive meaning of the law', Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 11(1): 23-45. Harris, M. Kay (1987) 'Moving into the new millennium: toward a feminist vision of justice', The Prison Journal 67: 27-38. Hayes, Hennessey and Kathleen Daly (2001) 'Family conferencing in South Australia and reoffending: preliminary results from the SAJJ project', Paper presented to Australian and New Zealand Society of Criminology Conference, Melbourne, February. <http://www.gu.edu.au/school/ccj/kdaly.html> Heidensohn, Frances (1986) 'Models of justice: Portia or Persephone? Some thoughts on equality, fairness and gender in the field of criminal justice', International Journal of the Sociology of Law 14: 287-98. Hudson, Barbara (1998) 'Restorative justice: the challenge of sexual and racial violence', Journal of Law and Society 25(2): 237-56. Hudson, Barbara (2001) 'Victims and offenders', Paper presented to Cambridge Seminar on Restorative Justice, Toronto, May. 39 Hudson, Joe, Allison Morris, Gabrielle Maxwell, and Burt Galaway (eds.) (1996) Family Group Conferences: Perspectives on Policy and Practice. Monsey, NY: Criminal Justice Press. Kurki, Leena (2001) 'Evaluation of restorative justice practices'. Paper presented to Cambridge Seminar on Restorative Justice, Toronto, May. La Prairie, Carol (1999) 'Some reflections on new criminal justice policies in Canada: restorative justice, alternative measures and conditional sentences', Australian and New Zealand Journal of Criminology 32(2): 139-52. Levrant, Sharon, Francis T. Cullen, Betsy Fulton, and John F. Wozniak (1999) 'Reconsidering restorative justice: the corruption of benevolence revisited?', Crime & Delinquency 45(1): 3-27. MacKinnon, Catharine (1987) Feminism Unmodified. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Marshall, Tony (1996) 'The evolution of restorative justice in Britain', European Journal of Criminal Policy and Research 4(4): 21-43. Masters, Guy and David Smith (1998) 'Portia and Persephone revisited: thinking about feeling in criminal justice', Theoretical Criminology 2(1): 5-27. Matthews, Roger (1988) 'Reassessing informal justice', in R. Matthews (ed.) Informal Justice?, pp. 1-24. Newbury Park, CA: Sage. Maxwell, Gabrielle and Allison Morris (1993) Family, Victims and Culture: Youth Justice in New Zealand. Wellington: Social Policy Agency and the Institute of Criminology, Victoria University of Wellington. Maxwell, Gabrielle and Allison Morris (1996) 'Research on family group conferences with young offenders in New Zealand', in J. Hudson et al. (eds.) Family Group Conferences: Perspectives on Policy & Practice, pp. 88-110. Monsey, NY: Willow Tree Press. 40 Maxwell, Gabrielle and Allison Morris (2000) 'Restorative justice and reoffending', in H. Strang and J. Braithwaite (eds.) Restorative Justice: Philosophy to Practice, pp. 93- 103. Aldershot: Ashgate/Dartmouth. McCold, Paul (2000) 'Toward a holistic vision of restorative juvenile justice: a reply to the maximalist model', Contemporary Justice Review 3(4): 357-414. Mead, George Herbert (1917-18) 'The psychology of punitive justice', The American Journal of Sociology 23: 577-602 [reprinted in The Sociology of Punishment, Dario Melossi (ed.)]. Miller, Seumas and John Blackler (2000) 'Restorative justice: retribution, confession and shame', in H. Strang and J. Braithwaite (eds.) Restorative Justice: Philosophy to Practice, pp. 77-91. Aldershot: Ashgate/Dartmouth. Morris, Allison and Gabrielle Maxwell (2001) (eds.) Restorative Justice for Juveniles: Conferencing, Mediation and Circles. Oxford: Hart Publishing Ltd. Nova Scotia Department of Justice (1998) Restorative Justice: A Program for Nova Scotia. Halifax: Department of Justice. O'Malley, Pat (1999) 'Volatile and contradictory punishment', Theoretical Criminology 3(2): 175-96. Pavlich, George C. (1996) Justice Fragmented: Mediating Community Disputes under Postmodern Conditions. New York: Routledge. Pratt, John (2000) 'The return of the wheelbarrow men; or, the arrival of postmodern penality?', British Journal of Criminology 40: 127-45. Shearing, Clifford (2001) 'Punishment and the changing face of the governance', Punishment & Society 3(2): 203-20. Sherman, Lawrence W., Heather Strang, and Daniel J. Woods (2000) Recidivism Patterns in the Canberra Reintegrative Shaming Experiments (RISE). Canberra: Centre for 41 Restorative Justice, Australian National University. <http://www.aic.gov.au/rjustice/rise/recidivism/index.html> Smart, Carol (1989) Feminism and the Power of Law. London: Routledge. Smart, Carol (1992) 'The woman of legal discourse', Social & Legal Studies 1(1): 29-44. South African Truth and Reconciliation Commission (1998) The Report of the Truth and Reconciliation Commission. <http://www.org.za/truth/report> Strang, Heather, Lawrence W. Sherman, Geoffrey C. Barnes, and John Braithwaite (1999) Experiments in Restorative Policing: A Progress Report to the National Police Research Unit on the Canberra Reintegrative Shaming Experiments (RISE). Canberra: Centre for Restorative Justice, Australian National University. <http://www.aic.gov.au/rjustice/rise/index.html> Tonry, Michael (1999) 'Rethinking unthinkable punishment policies in America', UCLA Law Review 46(4): 1751-91. Tyler, Tom R. (1990) Why People Obey the Law. New Haven: Yale University Press. Tyler, Tom R., Robert J. Boeckmann, Heather J. Smith, and Yuen J. Huo (1997) Social Justice in a Diverse Society. Boulder: Westview Press. Umbreit, Mark (1994) Victim Meets Offender: The Impact of Restorative Justice and Mediation. Monsey, NY: Criminal Justice Press. Van Ness, Daniel (1993) 'New wine and old wineskins: four challenges of restorative justice', Criminal Law Forum 4: 251-76. Van Ness, Daniel and Karen Strong (1997) Restoring Justice. Cincinnati: Anderson Publishing. Von Hirsch, Andrew (1993) Censure and Sanctions. New York: Oxford University Press. Walgrave, Lode (1995) 'Restorative justice for juveniles: just a technique or a fully fledged alternative?', The Howard Journal 34: 228-49. 42 Walgrave, Lode (2000) 'How pure can a maximalist approach to restorative justice remain? Or can a purist model of restorative justice become maximalist?', Contemporary Justice Review 3(4): 415-32. Walgrave, Lode and Ivo Aertsen (1996) 'Reintegrative shaming and restorative justice: interchangeable, complementary or different?', European Journal on Criminal Policy and Research 4: 67-85. Weitekamp, Elmar (1999) 'The history of restorative justice', in G. Bazemore and L. Walgrave (eds.) Restorative Juvenile Justice: Repairing the Harm of Youth Crime, pp. 75-102. Monsey, NY: Criminal Justice Press. Wright, Martin (1991) Justice for Victims and Offenders. Philadelphia: Open University Press. Zedner, Lucia (1994) 'Reparation and retribution: are they reconcilable?', Modern Law Review 57: 228-50. Zehr, Howard. (1995) 'Justice paradigm shift? Values and vision in the reform process', Mediation Quarterly 12(3): 207-16. 43 Notes 1 Indicative examples of advocates are Bazemore and Walgrave (1999), Braithwaite (1999),Consedine (1995), Umbreit (1994), Van Ness and Strong (1997), and Zehr (1995). Among the skeptics and critics are Ashworth (1993), Blagg (1997), Delgado (2000), Hudson (1998), Levrant et al. (1999), and Pavlich (1996). Because the modern idea of restorative justice is new, publications reporting findings from research are few. Among them are contributors in collections edited by Bazemore and Schiff (2001), Crawford and Goodey (2000), Hudson et al. (1996), and Morris and Maxwell (2001). 2 Conferences are meetings where an admitted offender(s), his/her supporters, a victim(s),his/her supporters, and relevant other people come together to discuss the offence, its impact, and what sanction (or reparation) is appropriate. The conference, which is run by a coordinator and attended by a police officer, is typically used as diversion from court prosecution, but it may also be used to give pre-sentencing advice to judges and magistrates. Police-run diversionary conferencing is highly atypical of Australian and New Zealand conferencing, whereas it is more typical in UK and North American practices. See Bargen (1996), Daly and Hayes (2001), and Hudson et al. (1996) for overviews of jurisdiction variation in Australia and New Zealand. 3 Even when calling for the need to 'blend restorative, reparative, and transformative justice ...with the prosecution of paradigmatic violations of human rights', Drumbl (2000: 296) is unable to avoid using the term 'retributive' to refer to responses that should be reserved for the few. 4 Drawing from Cottingham's (1979) analysis of retribution's many meanings, restorativejustice advocates tend to use retributivism to mean 'repayment' (to which they add a punitive 44 kick) whereas desert theorists, such as von Hirsch (1993), use retributivism to mean 'deserved' and would argue for decoupling retribution from punitiveness. 5 It is important to emphasise that new justice practices have not been applied to the factfindingstage of the criminal process; they are used almost exclusively for the penalty phase. Some comparative claims about restorative justice practices (e.g., they are not adversarial when retributive justice is) are misleading in that restorative justice attends only to the penalty phase when negotiation is possible. No one has yet sketched a restorative justice process for those who do not admit to an offence. 6 I became aware of the term new justice from LaPrairie's (1999) analysis of developments inCanada. She defines new justice initiatives as representing a 'shift away from a justice discourse of punitiveness and punishment toward one of reconciliation, healing, repair, atonement, and reintegration' (p. 147), and she sees such developments as part of a new emphasis on 'community' and 'partnership' as analysed by Crawford (1997). There may be better terms than the 'old' and 'new justice' (e.g., Hudson, 2001, suggests 'established criminal justice' for the old justice), but my general point is that the retributive/restorative couplet has produced, and continues to produce, significant conceptual confusion in the field. 7 Restorative justice advocates speak of the harm not of the crime, and in doing so, they elidea crucial distinction between a civil and criminal harm, the latter involving both a harm and a wrong (Duff, 2001). 8 In response to this point, one reader said there had to be some way to theorise varied justiceforms (both in an empirical and normative sense), and thus, the disappointment I speak of reflects a disenchantment with the theoretical enterprise to adequately reflect particularity and variation in the empirical social world. This is a longstanding problem in the sociological field. What troubles me, however, is the construction of theoretical terms in the justice field, which use dualisms in adversarial and oppositional relation to one another. 45 9 The major research studies in the region are Maxwell and Morris (1993) for New Zealand,Strang et al. (1999) for the ACT and the RISE project, and the results reported here for the SAJJ project in South Australia. See Daly (2001a) for a review of these and other studies. Space limitations preclude a review of the methods of each study and a detailed analysis of results. 10 It is important to distinguish jurisdictions like South Australia, New South Wales, and NewZealand, where conferences are routinely used from other jurisdictions (like Victoria and Queensland), where conferences are used selectively and in a relatively few number of cases (although Queensland practices are undergoing change as of April 2001). When conferences are used routinely, we should not expect to see 'restorativeness' emerging most of the time. 11 Space limitations preclude a review of the definitions and methods used in the re-offendingstudies; rather general findings are summarised. |
|
[bottom.htm] |