|
Is
Compulsive Buying a Real Disorder, and Is It Really Compulsive?
Am J Psychiatry
2006;163:1670-1672.
The article in this issue by Koran et
al. raises several intriguing questions regarding
a novel proposed
psychiatric disorder: compulsive buying. DSM
provides a working model of categories and diagnostic
criteria for psychiatric disorders. DSM is constantly
evolving and research planning is underway for DSM-V.
Changes to DSM-V being considered include the creation
of two broad new categories that may influence the
conceptualization of compulsive buying.
A category related to
obsessive-compulsive-related disorders might include
disorders such as obsessive compulsive disorder,
obsessive compulsive personality disorder, hoarding,
body dysmorphic disorder, eating disorders,
hypochondriasis, Tourette’s syndrome, Sydenham’s chorea
or pediatric autoimmune neuropsychiatric disorders
associated with streptococcal infections, and
pathological grooming disorders, such as
trichotillomania, skin picking, and nail biting.
Compulsive buying was not determined to be a good fit for this category. On the other hand, a parallel category under consideration is behavioral and substance addictions, which might include substance-related disorders and several impulse-control disorders (pathological gambling, pyromania, and kleptomania), as well as others currently in the category of impulse control disorders not otherwise specified (Internet addiction, impulsive-compulsive sexual behavior, and compulsive buying). The National Institute on Drug Abuse has considered behavioral addictions (such as compulsive buying) to be "cleaner" and more homogeneous models of substance addictions because these conditions may share clinical features and perhaps underlying brain circuitry, and these features and circuitry are not altered by the ingestion of exogenous substances. Similar phases seem to occur for behavioral and substance addictions: initially, episodes are characterized by increasing physiological and emotional arousal before the act; pleasure, high, or gratification associated with the act; and a decrease in arousal and feelings of guilt and remorse afterward. Tolerance and physiological withdrawal can also develop. Because an impulsive component (pleasure, arousal, or gratification) is involved in initiating the cycle, and a compulsive component is involved in the persistence of the behavior, these conditions may also be thought of as impulsive-compulsive disorders.
The creation of a condition such as
compulsive buying might be associated with controversy
and criticized by some as creating a trivial disorder; "medicalizing"
a "moral" problem or creating a new disorder in order to
sell more pharmaceuticals. Similar criticisms of
attention deficit hyperactivity disorder (ADHD) and
social anxiety disorder have been raised: that children
with minor and natural levels of excess activity should
not be "medicalized" or medicated or that because so
many people are socially anxious, this is a natural
trait not worthy of diagnosis or treatment. However, the
issues involved in creating new diagnoses is complex.
In this issue, Koran et al. reported
on a study of compulsive buying. They surveyed a large
random sample of U.S. adults to estimate a prevalence
rate and to characterize compulsive buyers. They and
others have proposed names and diagnostic criteria for
this problem and, as required for most DSM disorders,
the criteria include significant distress or functional
impairment, as well as criteria specific to the
disorder. As is typical at this stage, the specific name
and criteria differ from researcher to researcher and
study to study, complicating the development of
knowledge about the condition. Until a certain amount of
evidence of a new disorder is accumulated, not enough is
known to define criteria, but at a certain point, there
is enough information to propose criteria. Including a
disorder in DSM is very helpful for the advance of
knowledge because researchers can then use the defined
criteria in their new research, and the criteria can be
refined over time as more research is completed.
Clearly, the behavioral addictions or
impulse control disorders can be viewed from different
perspectives, including: a medical perspective; a moral,
ethical, or religious perspective; and a legal
perspective. These behaviors exist on a continuum,
perhaps in a normal distribution in the general
population, with many individuals having some of the
behaviors, a few showing none, and a few showing a great
deal. However, in a subgroup of individuals, a
biological vulnerability may result in impairment of
control that leads to behavioral excess or disinhibition
and is associated with significant levels of distress
and functional impairment. Consideration that shopping
is universal and making an unwise purchase from time to
time is common, although research has shown that there
are individuals whose compulsive buying is extreme and
leads to significant distress and impairment. Using
scores on the Compulsive Buying Scale
(1) of 2 standard deviations below the mean, Koran
et al. estimated the prevalence of compulsive buying to
be 5.8%; even with a very strict criterion of 3 standard
deviations below the mean, the prevalence would be 1.4%.
Previous estimates based on smaller, less representative
samples have ranged from 1.8% to 16%. Thus, whatever
estimate is used, the prevalence is higher than or
similar to disorders that receive considerable research
and clinical attention, and it represents a sizable
group suffering distress and or functional impairment.
The impairment criteria are important because it is how
compulsive buying as a disorder is differentiated from
more normal, if excessive, buying. Koran et al. found
that when using the criterion of 2 standard deviations
on the Compulsive Buying Scale, the individuals had
significantly more maladaptive shopping and buying
attitudes and behaviors and more financial problems than
the other respondents. The data for the group with 3
standard deviations shows consequences that were even
more extreme. This sort of distribution applies to many
disorders. As mentioned above, ADHD and social anxiety
disorder are two examples. One might also look at a
long-accepted disorder: major depressive disorder. Many
people suffer from occasional sadness and days on which
they are "blue," but that does not diminish the
importance of recognizing, researching, and treating
major depressive disorder.
One can ask if people are morally
responsible for their behavior if they commit unethical
acts because of what has been classified as a mental
disorder? Similarly, if an individual diagnosed with an
impulse control disorder does something illegal, is he
or she responsible? Having a diagnosable disorder does
not eliminate the moral or legal consequences of bad
behavior, although courts can require that the
individuals receive treatment in order to prevent a
recurrence of the problem. This can be seen with
alcoholism, which has long been considered a disorder.
If an alcoholic has an accident while driving under the
influence, that is not considered a mitigating
circumstance but the courts can require that the
individual undergo treatment for their alcohol problem,
along with any other sentencing requirements. Viewing
compulsive buying from a medical perspective and as a
diagnosable mental disorder has several advantages. It
might facilitate routine screening for the condition by
mental health professionals, and perhaps, even inclusion
of the disorder in national prevalence surveys, which
would help define the true prevalence of the disorder.
It might also lead to the study of vulnerability factors
for the development of the disorder, better
characterization of brain-based circuits, and the
development of effective psychosocial and medication
treatments. Although prevention of overdiagnosis or
possible misuse of diagnostic labels is important, these
concerns should be balanced against the advancement of
knowledge that could potentially lead to new treatments
or prevention strategies for serious human problems.
|
|
|