In recent weeks,
social inclusion has become a topic of some debate. This follows reports that,
subsequent to his appointment to the social inclusion portfolio in last year’s
front-bench reshuffle, Mark Butler was unable to define what social inclusion
means.
In response to an
article on social inclusion by Butler published late last year, Senator
Mitch Fifield and former Keating Government Minister Gary
Johns both criticised the term as being devoid of substance. Fifield went on
to propose that the Social Inclusion Board should be abolished, with the $3
million annual cost of the Board being allocated towards the $6.5 billion annual
cost of a disability insurance scheme.
The above comments beg the
question: What is meant by the term social inclusion, and is it as
inconsequential in policy making terms as Fifield and Johns suggest?
To
be fair to Butler, neither the term social inclusion nor the related term social
exclusion have been clearly defined. The meaning of social inclusion varies very
much according to the national and ideological contexts in which it is used.
Mark Butler is correct, then, in noting that social inclusion means different
things to different people. This is in large part because the concept of social
inclusion lacks a coherent theoretical core—that is, it is not based on a
unified body of knowledge and theory.
That said, it is nevertheless
possible to identify certain features of social inclusion that are generally
agreed upon. The concept of social inclusion is typically concerned
with:
• Disadvantaged people’s lack of opportunity to participate in
social, economic or political life—usually as a result of a lack of necessary
resources, rights, goods and services, and
•
The multi-dimensional nature
of social exclusion and deprivation, with social exclusion seen as being the
result of a combination of linked and mutually reinforcing problems such as
unemployment, limited education, low income, poor housing, poor health and
family breakdown.
This second feature differentiates the idea of social
inclusion from that of poverty, which focuses more narrowly on a lack of
financial well-being and income as the source of disadvantage. Hence, a social
inclusion approach to addressing disadvantage requires that the various related
elements of deprivation be tackled through ‘joined-up’ approaches, rather than
simply by making income transfers to disadvantaged people.
The idea of
social inclusion has been criticised for reasons other than its definitional
vagueness. For example, it has been argued that social inclusion is
•
focused narrowly on participation in paid employment, at the expense of other
possible forms of inclusion
• limited in scope and ambition to ‘getting
people over the line of social inclusion’, rather than attempting to address the
causes of social exclusion, and
• based on a top-down approach that
treats those people who are being included as passive objects of policy (and
thus, ironically, excluding them)
The above criticisms call into question
the value of using social inclusion as a framework for social policy. This is
because, for one thing, it is not clear that social inclusion adds terribly much
to existing approaches to social policy. Also, by virtue of its very logic,
social inclusion could actually serve to limit the ambitions of policy-makers
and citizens where it comes to addressing social disadvantage. Finally, the
concept offers no concrete or specific mechanism to those who are thought of as
excluded for overcoming their exclusion.
Despite these substantial
limitations, the concept of social inclusion is not without merit and, as
this Parliamentary Library paper argues, it has the potential to be
developed along more fruitful lines—largely through a focus on
participation.
The idea of participation is central to many attempts to
define social inclusion. Further, a number of authors have argued that it is
participation rather than inclusion that should be the main focus of efforts to
address social exclusion. This is largely because it is the active logic of
participation rather than the relatively passive logic of inclusion that is more
likely to help tackle social disadvantage and marginality. An approach based
around participation assumes that people have a need and a right to participate
in society and not just the workforce (rather than simply to ‘be included’), and
that, where necessary, resources should be provided to facilitate this
participation. But this then raises the question of how this participation
should be structured and guaranteed into the future.
In the paper, we
suggested that the idea of social citizenship may provide an answer to this
question and that in doing so it could be used to provide the grounding for a
more substantive social inclusion agenda.
According to influential 20th
century British sociologist T. H. Marshall, modern citizenship may be understood
as a status that is bestowed on all those who are full members of a community.
By virtue of this status, all members are equal with respect to the rights and
duties with which the status is endowed.
Social citizenship refers to the social
rights, obligations and institutions that play a role in developing and
supporting equality of status in the community. Thus, social citizenship is
concerned with the provision of resources (such as education) and with social
services (such as public health and housing services) that are necessary for
membership and participation in society. As such, social citizenship can be seen
as being central to the full exercise of citizenship, along with the civil and
political rights that it helps to support.
The key point is that the
idea of social citizenship could lend weight to a social inclusion agenda by
guaranteeing that disadvantaged people are provided with the resources necessary
for participation, as a right rather than as state benevolence. But, more than
this, based as it is on the idea of social rights and responsibilities,
social
citizenship could also provide a framework for people’s active participation in
shaping the society in which they live as well as its future form. This is
because social citizenship focuses attention away from ‘who gets what’ and onto
questions about how current arrangements might be renegotiated so as to achieve
equality of status and a better future for all citizens.
The proposed
national disability insurance scheme provides something of an example of what a
citizenship-based social inclusion policy approach might look like. For one
thing, the scheme would, like citizenship, be universal in its coverage,
recognising that all people share the risk of experiencing disability at some
point in their lives. The scheme is also driven by the rationale that people
with disability have a right to participate in the fullest possible sense in all
aspects of society, and that society has a responsibility to empower them to do
so. Further, this right to participate is one that is being claimed by people
with disability, with the proposed scheme having been the result of bottom-up
activism. The challenge of a citizenship-based social inclusion framework would
be to consider how similar policy initiatives might be developed and applied in
relation to other groups of people who suffer from disadvantage and
marginalisation.
In short, locating social inclusion within a social
citizenship framework could help to address those criticisms of the concept
outlined above and to broaden its scope and ambition. At the same time, through
its focus on bringing about change at the micro-level through joined-up models
of service delivery and a more sophisticated understanding of the multiple
sources of disadvantage social inclusion could complement the concept of social
citizenship, which does not concern itself with such matters.